home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Kant: the Universal Law Formation of the Categorical Imperative
-
- Kantian philosophy outlines the Universal Law Formation of the
- Categorical Imperative as a method for determining morality of actions.
- This formula is a two part test. First, one creates a maxim and
- considers whether the maxim could be a universal law for all rational
- beings. Second, one determines whether rational beings would will it to
- be a universal law. Once it is clear that the maxim passes both prongs
- of the test, there are no exceptions. As a paramedic faced with a
- distraught widow who asks whether her late husband suffered in his
- accidental death, you must decide which maxim to create and based on the
- test which action to perform. The maxim "when answering a widow's
- inquiry as to the nature and duration of her late husbands death, one
- should always tell the truth regarding the nature of her late husband's
- death" (M1) passes both parts of the Universal Law Formation of the
- Categorical Imperative. Consequently, according to Kant, M1 is a moral
- action.
- The initial stage of the Universal Law Formation of the Categorical
- Imperative requires that a maxim be universally applicable to all
- rational beings. M1 succeeds in passing the first stage. We can easily
- imagine a world in which paramedics always answer widows truthfully when
- queried. Therefore, this maxim is logical and everyone can abide by it
- without causing a logical impossibility. The next logical step is to
- apply the second stage of the test.
- The second requirement is that a rational being would will this maxim
- to become a universal law. In testing this part, you must decide whether
- in every case, a rational being would believe that the morally correct
- action is to tell the truth. First, it is clear that the widow expects
- to know the truth. A lie would only serve to spare her feelings if she
- believed it to be the truth. Therefore, even people who would consider
- lying to her, must concede that the correct and expected action is to
- tell the truth. By asking she has already decided, good or bad, that she
- must know the truth.
- What if telling the truth brings the widow to the point where she
- commits suicide, however? Is telling her the truth then a moral action
- although its consequence is this terrible response? If telling the
- widow the truth drives her to commit suicide, it seems like no rational
- being would will the maxim to become a universal law. The suicide is,
- however, a consequence of your initial action. The suicide has no
- bearing, at least for the Categorical Imperative, on whether telling the
- truth is moral or not. Likewise it is impossible to judge whether upon
- hearing the news, the widow would commit suicide. Granted it is a
- possibility, but there are a multitude of alternative choices that she
- could make and it is impossible to predict each one. To decide whether
- rational being would will a maxim to become a law, the maxim itself must
- be examined rationally and not its consequences. Accordingly, the maxim
- passes the second test.
- Conversely, some people might argue that in telling the widow a lie,
- you spare her years of torment and suffering. These supporters of "white
- lies" feel the maxim should read, "When facing a distraught widow, you
- should lie in regards to the death of her late husband in order to spare
- her feelings." Applying the first part of the Universal Law Formation of
- the Categorical Imperative, it appears that this maxim is a moral act.
- Certainly, a universal law that prevents the feelings of people who are
- already in pain from being hurt further seems like an excellent
- universal law. Unfortunately for this line of objection, the only reason
- a lie works is because the person being lied to believes it to be the
- truth. In a situation where every widow is lied to in order to spare her
- feelings, then they never get the truth. This leads to a logical
- contradiction because no one will believe a lie if they know it a lie
- and the maxim fails.
- Perhaps the die-hard liar can regroup and test a narrower maxim. If it
- is narrow enough so that it encompasses only a few people, then it
- passes the first test. For example, the maxim could read, "When facing a
- distraught widow whose late husband has driven off a bridge at night,
- and he struggled to get out of the car but ended up drowning, and he was
- wearing a brown suit and brown loafers, then you should tell the widow
- that he died instantly in order to spare her feelings." We can easily
- imagine a world in which all paramedics lied to widows in this specific
- situation.
- That does not necessarily mean that it will pass the second test
- however. Even if it does pass the first test, narrowing down maxim can
- create other problems. For instance circumstances may change and the
- people who were originally included in the universal law, may not be
- included anymore. Consequently you many not want to will your maxim to
- be a universal law. Likewise, if one person can make these maxims that
- include only a select group of people, so can everyone else. If you
- create a maxim about lying to widows that is specific enough to pass the
- first test, so can everyone else. One must ask if rational beings would
- really will such a world in which there would be many, many specific,
- but universal, laws. In order to answer this question, one must use the
- rational "I" for the statement "I, as a rational being would will such a
- world," not the specific, embodied "I" which represents you in your
- present condition. You must consider that you could be the widow in the
- situation rather than the paramedic, then decide whether you would will
- such a universal law.
- I agree with the morality based on Kantian principles because it is
- strict in its application of moral conduct. Consequently there is no
- vacillating in individual cases to determine whether an action is moral
- or not. An action is moral in itself not because of its consequences but
- because any rational being wills it to be a universal law and it does
- not contradict itself. Regardless of what the widow does with the
- information, the act of telling her the truth, is a moral one. No one
- would argue that telling the truth, if she asks for it, is an immoral
- thing to do. Sometimes moral actions are difficult, and perhaps in this
- situation it would be easier to lie to the widow, but it would still be
- an immoral action that I would not want everyone to do. This picture of
- morality resonates with my common sense view of morality. If the widow
- subsequently commits suicide or commits any other immoral act as a
- consequence, that has no bearing on the morality of the original action
- in itself.
- Utilitarianism would differ on this point. Utilitarianism outlines that
- an action is moral if it increases the total happiness of society.
- Morality is based on consequences. Telling a lie to the widow would
- increase her happiness and consequently would, at least possibly, be a
- moral action. Utilitarianism would also take into account the precedent
- set by lying; however, the analysis still rests on predicted consequence
- rather than on the action's intrinsic moral value. The morality of
- telling the lie is on a case by case basis. In some situations, it might
- be better to tell the truth, and according to utilitarianism that would
- then be the moral action. Unlike Kantian philosophy, one is not bound by
- an immutable universal law. Instead one must judge in each case which
- action will produce the most overall happiness. The problem with this
- approach is that morality loses any value as a universal or intrinsic
- quality. Every decision is made on an individual basis in an individual
- and specific situation. In fact, utilitarianism considers happiness to
- be the only intrinsically valuable end.
- Defenders of utilitarianism claim that it maintains universality by
- considering the greatest happiness of all beings, rather than just
- individual happiness. Still, the morality is based on constantly
- changing and often unpredictable consequences. The requirement that one
- consider all of the consequences of an action and determine the best
- possible action through such calculations makes me reject utilitarianism
- as a method of determining morality.
- Although utilitarianism often offers the easier solution to perform
- because it produces immediate gratification and allows many exceptions
- to common sense moral codes, the answers it gives are unfilling and
- unrealistic. Furthermore, it is difficult, if not impossible, to make
- all of the required calculations beforehand. Kant's solution, although
- as interpreted by Kant is sometimes overly extreme, is much better than
- utilitarianism. It resonates with my moral sensibilities to consider
- that actions are moral or immoral regardless of their immediate
- consequences. I am willing to accept that sometimes the moral action is
- harder to perform, but I am unwilling to accept that morality rests
- within the specifics of a situation and the possible consequences.
- Therefore, I consider Kant's Universal Law Formation of the Categorical
- Imperative to be a better test of morality than Mill's Utilitarianism.
-